Lords judgment: Home Secretary v AF

I said I’d write about the case; and now, finally, I am doing. Here’s last week’s judgment about control order. There’s also the podcast I recorded with Charon QC about it, don’t forget.

I must admit, I was surprised by this judgment: I wrote eighteen months ago about a similar case, also involving one of these appellants (AF), which at the time I thought had much the same result as last week’s case – ruling that an appeal to SIAC from a control order is in breach of the right to a fair hearing if the case against the controllee is mainly based on secret material. It seems I was wrong in reading the case that way, because three of their Lordships who were involved in both cases – Lady Hale, Lord Carswell and Lord Brown – say that’s not what they meant. Oh, well. I take comfort in the fact that they needed to explain that, and that Lady Hale admits that whatever it was she wanted to say in MB, she didn’t say it clearly enough.

This time there can be no doubt the Lords have decided – nine of them, unanimously – that a controlee must be gven sufficient information about the allegations against him if his appeal to SIAC under the Prevention of Terrorism Act 2005 is to be fair. They were applying the European Court of Human Rights in A v UK, which laid down that principle in a case involving the legislation that preceded the 2005 Act – and which was ruled incompatible with Convention rights by the Lords in 2004.

I say the Lords were unanimous, and indeed they were: all agreed A v UK must be followed. But Lord Hoffmann said in terms that he thinks Strasbourg has got this wrong; I think he’s right to say this if he thinks so, although I also think the logic of that is that he should also decline to follow Strasbourg – since the Human Rights Act only obliges him to take A v UK into account. His approach is interesting, though, and I especially liked the way he brought God into it (see paragraph 72). I have to say I have a fair amount of sympathy with him and with the Home Secretary’s probable frustration with this ruling. While it is almost certainly safe to disclose more than the Home Office currently does (I reckon this is almost always true), there must also be a risk that disclosure will give away details of informants or of information that is not known to the security services, and so endanger lives.

The judgment certainly makes it difficult to maintain the current control orders regime. But I expect several further rounds of litigation. Why? Because to say that controlees must be told enough about the allegations against them to be able to instruct lawyers is not the same as saying exactly how much needs to be disclosed in order to achieve that. If the Home Office decides to make further disclosures, I expect controlees to claim the material is insufficient; and I think it would be cowardly for the Lords, or the Supreme Court as it will be by then, to decline to give clear guidance. If AF has to go back to them a third time, that will be bad enough; to risk his having to come a fourth time would be judicial irresponsibility.

One more thought: I’m not satisfied by the way the Lords have dealt with interpretation under section 3 of the Human Rights Act. In the original case I criticised them for this, but they seem not to be reading (why not?) because they’ve gone and made the same mistake again. Lord Scott is the only one of them (see para. 95) to consider whether the special advocate procedure and withholding of secret material might be a fundamental feature of the 2005 Act, and so not capable of being “read down”. I don’t think his approach is correct: he seems to think the language of the provisions determines how they must be read (which, though it sounds paradoxical, is the wrong approach according to the leading case, Ghaidan). And he allows the parties to decide the issue for him. But the others are surely wrong not even to think about the point.

Charon QC podcast: Home Secretary v AF

Charon interviewed me this morning about Wednesday’s House of Lords judgment in Home Secretary v AF, in which they ruled, applying the ECtHR judgment in A v UK, that there is a breach of the article 6 Convention right in proceedings under the Prevention of Terrorism Act 2005 if a control order is imposed and, on appeal to the Special Immigration Appeals Commission a “controlee” is unable to effectively to challenge the order because the essence of the case against him is kept secret for reasons of national security.

I’ll write about the judgment, probably tomorrow evening (apologies – work commitments have kept me away); in the meantime, listen to the podcast here.

Reporting crime

I must post briefly on something that’s annoyed me: George Alagiah just said, summarising the day’s headlines on BBC News, that the murderers Sonnex and Farmer were sentenced to 40 and 35 years respectively. They weren’t. They were sentenced to serve a minimum of 40 and of 35 years respectively. They could serve longer. I can understand the parents feeling even that’s not enough, but it’d be great, wouldn’t it, if broadcasters at least reported the sentences accurately.

UPDATE: I’m glad to say he got it right just before half past, saying they’d got “at least” 40 and 35 years.

2009-06-04T18:16:00+00:00Tags: |

Vodafone 2 v HMRC

I’m quite interested in the Court of Appeal’s recent decision in this tax case, about Vodafone’s attempt to structure its takeover of Mannesman in the most tax-efficient way, using a Luxembourg-registered holding company to take advantage of lower rates in that country. The issue was whether the British tax legislation on “controlled foreign companies”, designed to enable the taxman to collect tax here in any event (minus the tax paid in Luxembourg) had to be disapplied as incompatible with EU law on freedom of establishment in the light of the ECJ’s ruling in C-196/04 Cadbury-Schweppes. The Court decided it should not be disapplied, as it can be read consistently with EU obligations so long as an exception from British taxation is read in for genuine, economically active European companies rather than merely artificial arrangements. Quite interesting from a tax point of view.

More interesting from a broader public law perspective is the way the Court approaches its task of interpretation. In deciding it could properly read an exception in to the tax legislation, applying the EU Marleasing principle of consistent interpretation, ultimately as a result of section 2(4) of the European communities Act 1972, the Court was guided by the law on interpretation under section 3 of the Human Rights Act, the Chancellor Sir Andrew Morritt explaining (para. 41) that

The terms of that section are in substance the same as the terms of s.2(4) ECA 1972 although the consequence of an inability to find a conforming interpretation is a declaration of incompatibility not disapplication in the manner I have explained.

He must be right: the similarity of the two provisions was pointed out by Lord Steyn in the leading human rights interpretation case, Ghaidan, which is referred to in the judgment. In the early days of the Human Rights Act, lawyers would look to EU law on consistent interpretation to construct arguments about what was possible under section 3 of the Human Rights Act; now the analogy seems to be the other way.

2009-06-04T11:25:00+00:00Tags: , , , |

Toying with the constitution

Chris Hawes at The Wardman Wire has written an excellent piece today on constitutional reform arguing against some of the fads of the moment, like proportional representation and fixed-term parliaments. I’ve already written about fixed terms; and I agree with him about PR, too. The right place for it in our system would be in the House of Lords. To have the Commons elected by PR would risk a politicians’ politics of permanent coalition, in which MPs, not voters, choose who will govern, where we will be unable to sack the government, and where our influence over it will be smaller even than it is now. What PR can usefully do, though, is prevent the tyranny of the majority; that’s why it’s perfect for a revising and delaying chamber.

I’m not against all constitutional change. Devolution is a good thing, I think (although there is an English dimension yet to be resolved – I’d have only English/English & Welsh MPs voting on purely English/English & Welsh matters), and I back the Human Rights Act and freedom of information. I wouldn’t oppose a bit more use of the referendum, open primaries for Parliamentary selection, or a recall mechanism as long as it’s triggered by some independent finding of misconduct in office, rather than just political opposition. Tinkering is good.

But what Britain faces now is a political crisis, not a constitutional one, and politicians desperate to cling on to power should not be allowed to use it to toy with the constitution in their own narrow interests. If Alan Johnson is Prime Minister next week, he should not take that as any sort of mandate to bring in PR: that would be an obviously self-serving move from a Labour Party whose best hope of avoiding years or wilderness could be to offer this sacrifice, and coalition, to the LibDems.

Meanwhile, this week’s Prime Minister has launched a laughable “Council on Democratic Renewal” which seems to consist of ministers themselves plus a few great and good invited speakers. The only purpose of this stunt is to allow Brown to pose as “ahead of the curve”. It is the least democratic possible way to propose any reform, and this fag-packet “council” should meet as little as possible.

In particular, the suggestion Britain should have a written constitution is especially dangerous. It may be a superficially attractive idea: it sounds so “modern”, doesn’t it? But many people fail to realise it would mean a total constitutional revolution, abandoning what’s long been the keystone of our democracy: Parliamentary sovereignty. In countries with written consitutions, it is that written document which is sovereign – not democratic institutions nor, ultimately, the people who elect them. In countries like the US and Germany it is unelected judges who determine policy on smoking bans, abortion and gun ownership; in the States, it’s beyond doubt that Justice Scalia is one of the most powerful people in the country. Who elected him? It would be a disaster if Lord Phillips were as powerful here.

I’m a great admirer of the German and American constitutions, believe it or not: both countries had good reasons for adopting written consitutions at the moment they did, each is about as good a system as can be consciously devised by men, and each has stood the test of time. Americans are rightly proud of a system that has worked so well for two hundred years. But Britain’s constitution in the 21st century should not be based on the political ideas of the eighteenth; nor do we need arrangements designed above all to prevent the return of fascist dictatorship. Our constitution has the advantage of having evolved over time – and it has indeed evolved since King and Parliament vied for power, a contest that’s still built in to the American constitution’s frozen music. We’ve moved on since then.

Parliamentary sovereignty is a good, soundly democratic principle. People here would miss it, and only realise what they had when it’d gone. Politicians should stop toying with the fundamentals of the constitution.

Mrinal Patel and the Fraud Act 2006

You may remember that last week Mrs. Patel appeared at Harrow Magistrates’ Court; she’s being prosecuted by Harrow Council under section 2 of the Fraud Act 2006, the accusation being that she gave a false address in order to get her son into a particular school. She’s pleaded not guilty, and says she was genuinely living at her mother’s at the relevant time.

First of all, aside from this particular case, let me say I have no difficulty in principle with this kind of prosecution. I can well imagine that parents do lie sometimes to gain places at desirable schools, and I disagree that merely rescinding the place is enough to tackle this. If that’s all councils did about it, then parents who cheat would be no worse off for their cheating; you might as well cheat, because the very worst possible outcome would be the same as if you’d acted honestly in the first place. I wouldn’t be at all happy with that, and (unpopular though it is at the moment) I’d much rather allow councils to use legal powers to investigate – if need be by surveillance – and prosecute any offences, than to see social advantage gained by lies. Because if you’re relaxed about this sort of parental behaviour, it means you’re relaxed about the fact that the children of honest parents are as a result sent to worse schools and perhaps worse lives. Compared to that injustice, the impact of councils’ action on the civil liberties of a few parents is laughably insignificant.

But legally, I’m interested in the charge here. Under section 2, fraud is only committed if a false representation is made with intent to gain, or cause loss to another; and section 5 makes clear that means gain or loss in money or other property. To convict, then, in a case like this, the council must succeed in arguing that a school place is some sort of property (even assuming it can prove any false representation has been made in the first place, which Mrs. Patel denies of course). But is it? Property needn’t be a tangible thing – copyright is a form of property, for instance – but it seems a stretch to see a school place as an enforceable right or entitlement akin to property. The alternative would be to argue that wrongly allocating a school place would somehow mean the council lost money – but surely it costs the same to allocate a place to one child as it does another.

No wonder there’ll be legal argument at the hearing on 8 July.

2009-06-02T10:10:00+00:00Tags: , , |

Thoughts on Proposition 8

Last Tuesday, the California Supreme Court decided to uphold “Proposition 8”, an amendment to the state’s constitution passed by a referendum last November. Here’s the opinion, and a press release summarising it. Proposition 8 amends the constitution so as to restrict marriage to opposite-sex couples; it was a response to last year’s decision by the court giving gay couple a constitutional right to marry, and has successfully removed that right. Dick Carpenter at Volokh Conspiracy was among those who successfully predicted this outcome.

The arguments were as follows. First, it was said Proposition 8 was not valid as it amounted to a revision rather than a mere amendment to the state constitution. Second, it was argued equality is an inalienable right under the constitution, so that it can’t be amended out, at least without some compelling public interest. Finally it was argued that the amendment violates the separation of powers doctrine fundamental to American constitutional thinking, by re-adjudicating, in effect, the issue that the court decided a year ago, i.e. whether gay couples have a constitutional right to marry. The 6-1 majority rejected all these arguments. Proposition 8 is indeed an amendment rather than a wholesale constitutional revision; the constitution’s description of certain rights as inalienable does not preclude constitutional amendments to them; and the constitutional right of the people to amend the constitution does not usurp the function of the judiciary. However, Proposition 8 is prospective rather than retrospective, so that gay marriages entered into before in came into force remain valid.

I don’t claim any expertise in the constitution of California, but the opinion looks to me obviously sound. If changing the rules on who can marry were a revision of the constitution, rather than an amendment, it raises serious questions about how the court could have gone so far as to revise the constitution last year. But anyway, the change is clearly not of such a scale. The other two grounds of challenge seem to me just to be ways of trying to defeat the clear constitutional provision provision for amendment by public initiative. From the point of view of a British public lawyer, anyway, the complaint seemed founded on hopeless creativity. Equally, the application of the interpretative presumption against retroactivity also seems unimpeachable.

I have a number of thoughts leading from this.

Let me make it clear I support gay marriage; in that sense, I’m sorry California will no longer allow it. But I’m glad the court has decided the way it has, firstly because I think it’s legally correct, and secondly, because in general I think it’s preferable for social changes like gay marriage to come in through the ballot-box and legislation, rather than through judicial decision. I can see that some advocates of minority rights might say my approach would mean slower progress in a liberal direction: cases like Roe v Wade achieved things that never would have come about by legislation. That’s a strong point. My answer is that trusting in a written consitutions and in judges to interpret them may lead to Roe v Wade, but it may also lead to District of Columbia v Heller, which hardly represented progress. My preference is really just the traditional British preference for Parliamentary sovereignty and an unwritten consitution, two things that go together inseparably.

Second, some British writers (I’m thinking of Alastair Campbell) have criticised the opinion as though it shows California were somehow behind Britain in terms of gay unions – but I don’t think that’s right. California has already legislated for domestic partnerships. I realise they’re not the same as marriage; but then British civil partnerships, although nearer to equality with marriage, aren’t exactly the same either. California is ahead of us in simply having a debate about treating gay and straight couples equally in all respects.

Finally, I think this debate will come to us in the UK before long, and unfortunately it will come in the form of litigation. Wilson and Kitzinger may have failed in their attempt to have their Canadian marriage declared valid in the UK, but the European Convention on Human Rights is a “living instrument”, to be interpreted in the light of changing social conditions – there is no Scalia-style originalism in Strasbourg. So the more European countries provide for gay marriages or recognise such marriages entered into abroad, the more difficult it will be for the UK to refuse recognition.

Finally, the unexploded, ticking bomb here is EU Directive 2004/38 on the free movement rights of EU citizens and their families. Look at articles 2, 3 and 4: they give an unconditional right of free movement within Europe not only to every EU citizen but to his or her spouse – a term which is undefined. But there can be no doubt that the parties to a same-sex marriage contracted in, say, the Netherlands, are spouses, not registered partners; and interpreting the Directive purposively and against the background of the general EU law principle of equal treatment, it seems to me impossible to read it in a way which excludes some spouses on the basis of their sex or sexuality. At some point, someone’s same-sex spouse is going to establish the right of entry, say to a conservative country like Malta; and it will be clear that the UK, too, must recognise gay marriages as such, at least for EU law purposes.

2009-06-01T13:39:00+00:00Tags: , , |

Fixed-term Parliaments: not the answer

One of the strangest aspects of the MP’s expenses scandal has been the way politicians have tried to move public discussion on to questions of sweeping constitutional reform. It seems to me it was the greed of MPs themselves – though not all of them, of course – and the laxness of the system they created for themselves, that caused this abuse of public funds, and that it was the attempt by some of them, including the Speaker, to cover up the abuse that has made public anger even worse. Nothing about it points to the need for deep constitutional reform.

That doesn’t mean the ideas people are floating don’t have merit: some of them certainly do.

But an idea I’m definitely not in favour of is one David Cameron has now said he’ll consider: fixed-term Parliaments. The first thing to say about this is that it’s entirely at odds with Cameron’s desire for there to be a general election now. This contradiction in itself seems to me to make David Cameron’s new suggestion laughable. But I’m not for it on its merits, either.

We already have fixed-term Parliaments in the sense that Parliament has a fixed maximum term, under the Septennial Act 1715 (a silly bit of drafting, that – surely the 1715 Act ought to have been repealed and replaced, rather than simply amended). Parliament lasts a maximum of five years. What the reformers mean of course is that the Prime Minister should no longer have power to ask the Queen for a dissolution within five years, or a shortened four-year term.

But if you applied that rule strictly, as in David Howarth’s bill, then Parliament could not be dissolved (see clause 2(4)), and no new election could be held, even if a government lost its majority and was defeated in a vote of confidence. If the government resigned, a new administration would have to be formed by the opposition, or by a coalition of parties, without there being any possibility of the public having their say in a general election. Nothing could be less democratic. Britain would suffer either from lame-duck governments, staggering on but not governing, in a Parliament unable either to legislate or dissolve itself, or else from an even worse evil, changes of government without general elections. People complain enough about Gordon Brown becoming PM without holding an election soon after; what they’d say about getting David Cameron without an election, I don’t know.

So, some people say, we must have an exception in the event of a government losing a confidence vote. In those circumstances, the PM would be able to ask for a dissolution. Well, all right. But then the government would simply be able to vote itself out of office, as Gerhard Schröder’s red-green coalition did in Germany in 2005, whenever it thought an election convenient. The exception would ride a coach and horses through the rule.

So you can’t really ensure power changes hands by elections, and remove the PM’s power to cut and run. Is there anything in the idea simply of reducing Parliaments to four-year terms in place of the current five years? I don’t think so. British government is short-termist enough as it is. I wouldn’t want to exacerbate that problem by forcing a shorter time-horizon on it.

Really, what most people mean at the moment when they talk about fixed-term Parliaments is that they think after four years, this government’s had it and they want an election now. Well, if people want Labour out, they need to vote for someone else on June 4 – and hope to force a crisis at the top of government. Or else simply wait for the chance to sack ministers next year.

What makes no sense is to say that the inability to force an early election on Gordon Brown now means we should remove the possibility of an early general election ever being held in future.

2009-05-28T16:57:00+00:00Tags: , , |

R (Smith) v Defence Secretary: a judicial frolic

Since last week’s judgment in Smith – in which the Court of Appeal ruled that the Human Rights Act, in particular article 2, applies to British troops even on the battlefield, I’ve been thinking about the judgment (one reason why I’ve not blogged for several days) and I’m troubled by it. The Court’s conclusion – that British forces themselves are always personally within British jurisdiction, regardless of whether they’re within an area subject to British authority, and are therefore protected by the ECHR from violations by the UK, including breaches of the right to life on the battlefieldmay be vindicated one day in Strasbourg. I’m not sure. But the real puzzle here is why the Administrative Court and the Court of Appeal have thought fit to make such a ruling themselves in this case, and how they’ve come to the conclusion they have. The point is entirely hypothetical, and it’s neither necessary nor desirable for the courts to rule on it now. They’ve departed from authority, too.

The case is about the death of Private Jason Smith, who died of heatstroke on a British base in Basra. He was not killed on the battlefield or in conflict. The government concedes that in these circumstances, the article 2 Convention right to life applied to him, based on the decisions of the ECtHR in Bankovic and the House of Lords in Al-Skeini. The UK is clearly has authority and control on UK bases abroad; therefore, the inquest into Private Smith’s death should comply with the procedural requirement of an investigation following a death subject to article 2. So much was agreed in the Administrative Court – and you might think that was the end of the case.

But no. At first instance, Collins J was persuaded by counsel for Private Smith’s mother to decide whether British forces enjoy Convention rights wherever they might be – even though on the facts of the case the point is entirely academic. He decided, in a poorly reasoned passage (paras. 7-20 of his judgment) that they do. I say “poorly reasoned” because, firstly, Collins J does not explain why he considers it desirable to answer the question; secondly because the parallels he draws with employment law (para. 16) and courts martial (para. 17) are not good ones. In the employment situation we are normally dealing with contracts subject to domestic law, and courts martial always necessarily take place where the UK military courts have authority.

It also seems to me his ruling on the point is wrong, and arguably per incuriam in that it’s clearly at odds with the approach of the House of Lords in Al-Skeini. In that case the Lords, while divided on the scope of application of the Human Rights Act, unanimously took the view that it was wrong for a British court to extend the scope of application of the ECHR beyond what Strasbourg case-law clearly requires in a way that would affect other states. The best possible example of such a ruling would be to apply the ECHR on a personal basis to troops wherever they are in the world, even in conflict – as Collins J did. Extraordinarily, he cited Lord Rodger’s speech in Al-Skeini in support of his approach, although it’s clear that, at the relevant point in his speech (paras. 37-59) Lord Rodger was dealing with a different point, namely whether the Human Rights Act can apply at all in Iraq. It’s quite clear that Lord Rodger’s approach to Bankovic (paras. 60-81) does not support Collins J; on the contrary.

An unnecessary and bad decision, then. Yet the Court of Appeal has compounded the difficulty. Again, it cites Lord Rodger in Al-Skeini in support of its judgment, yet it ignores the key passage in his speech in which he rejected any extension of Strasbourg’s essentially territorial approach to the application of the Convention. The Court of Appeal considers itself bound by Lord Brown’s analysis of Bankovic (see para. 21 of the Court of Appeal’s judgment) at para. 109 of his speech, yet it ignores paras. 105-107 and 127-129 of his speech, which clearly reject anything other than a narrow, territorial approach to jurisdiction. The Court of Appeal’s support for a personal basis of jurisdiction simply cannot be reconciled with the clear reasoning of the House of Lords in Al-Skeini; and in the face of that authority it is simply not good enough for the Court of Appeal to say it is answering the relevant questions in a broad and commonsense way (para. 28). The resort to that kind of justification in itself demonstrates that the Court of Appeal has fallen well below the level of legal analysis required.

And quite apart from the bad legal analysis both courts have relied on, the utterly absurd nature of this judicial exercise is shown by paragraph 27 of its judgment, in which the Court says it is assuming for the purposes of its judgment that Private Smith – contrary to the true facts – died outside a British base.

The upshot is that we have a badly-reasoned, wrong appeal ruling on a purely hypothetical legal point which has never actually arisen. Nothing could be more Dickensian. This is an unjustified, wrong-headed judicial frolic, and I hope the Lords puts the genie back in its box. The question whether troops are entitled to human rights protection in battle should be settled when a real case arises, and preferably in Strasbourg.

Something else I’ve been thinking about is the precedent value of the Court of Appeal’s judgment as it stands, pending the Lords appeal. I’ve already said I think it may be per incuriam; if I’m right about that, it’s no precedent at all. Some might say the per incuriam rule doesn’t strictly apply, as the Court was neither ignorant nor forgetful of Al Skeini but purported, however wrongly, to apply it. Fair enough. In any event, though, as was once written by Professor Llewellyn (as cited in Cross and Harris’s Precedent in English Law):

There is a distinction between the ratio decidendi, the court’s own version of the rule of the case, and the true rule of the case, to wit what it will be made to stand for by another later court.

And as the editors of that book say on the previous page:

There are… many instances in which the rule of law forming the basis of a decision ceases to be the rule of law for which the case is binding authority because judges in later cases have… [interpreted]… the decision in the light of the facts of the case and other relevant judgments. …. The process of interpretation is most likely to occur when the original ratio decidendi was a wide one for, to quite Professor Glanville Williams, “Courts do not accord to their predecessors an unlimited power of laying down wide rules”.

No doubt the Court of Appeal’s version of its own ratio is the wide rule that British troops are always personally subject to the ECHR; in the light of the facts of the case itself and all other applicable authorities, however, that simply cannot be maintained as the true rule of the case. Before the House of Lords rules, and with any luck reverses it, the wide rule laid down in the appeal judgment should not be followed.

2009-05-28T15:10:00+00:00Tags: , , |

The Speaker: wholly inadequate

The Speaker’s statement today was an embarrassing affair: he read an apology to the public over MPs’ expenses, saying words that seemed not to come from his heart. He then said he’d act by summoning yet another meeting, weeks if not months too late, before proceeding to ignore entirely the issue of his own future. In responding to members’ points of order – no actual questions being permitted – he chose to hide behind procedures, saying Douglas Carswell MP’s motion of confidence in him could not be debated because technically it’s an “early day motion”.

I thought he should have resigned a year ago when he refused to allow debate on his own decision to appeal the Information Tribunal’s decision on – guess what – MPs’ expenses. Since then, he’s blamed the Serjeant-at-Arms for the search of Damian Green’s office in a cowardly statement in December, and he’s called the police in, not to investigate MPs but, incredibly, the leak to the Daily Telegraph. It was clear this morning that he is not the person to lead the Commons out of this awful expenses affair, and that he’s lost the confidence of many members. But now his shocking performance this afternoon has made his departure inevitable.

The statement was wholly inadequate. Martin is too small for this job, especially now, and surely must go. If he has any sense he’ll resign before he’s defenestrated.

2009-05-18T17:08:00+00:00Tags: |
Go to Top